|
|
Contents
of Part 5
2.2.6. The Republic
2.2.7. Preliminary Conclusions on Plato's Socrates
2.3. Xenophon
3. Conclusions
3.1. Plato as Philosopher or Mystic
3.2. Plato's Socratic Dialogues as a Proximity Text
3.3. Xenophon's Evidence
3.4. Socrates as Mystic
3.5. Socrates and Jesus
3.6. Jnani, Gnosis, and Philosophy in the West
3.7. Further Research
References
for part 5
2.2.6. The Republic
Plato's Republic
presents us with a different picture of Socrates than the one we have
drawn from the previous three dialogues. Many elements of this picture
are consistent with our portrait of Socrates as jnani, but
the Republic taken as a whole introduces a jarring note. The Republic
is unusual amongst Socratic dialogues for placing Socrates in the first
person, so one might suspect that it would provide the more reliable evidence
about him. However, the essential problem with it, from the perspective
of mysticism, is that it is Utopian. In fact it is one of the earliest
Utopian works and highly influential through Western political history.
The central proposition is the foundation of a State based on 'philosopher-kings',
where the term 'philosopher' here easily translates to mystic, as the
following statement from Socrates shows:
Because
the true philosopher, as you know, Adeimantus, whose mind is on higher
realities, has no time to look at the affairs of men, or to take part
in their quarrels with all the jealousy and bitterness they involve.
His eyes are turned to contemplate fixed and immutable realities, a
realm where there is no injustice done or suffered, but all is reason
and order, and which is the model which he imitates and to which he
assimilates himself as far as he can. For is there any way to stop a
man assimilating himself to anything with which he enjoys dealing? [73]
The description of a philosopher, whose mind is on higher realities and
whose eyes are turned to contemplate fixed and immutable realities is
consistent with mysticism, but the thrust of the Republic, that
such individuals should head the State is unusual in mysticism. Krishna,
according to the Gita and the Mahabharata played an active
role in the great war of Kurukshetra (though his actions were certainly
not that of the average local king), and Mohammed led his tribe to military
victory in the Middle East. Socrates himself was a foot-soldier. But a
philosopher-king? He even admits that most philosophers 'are rogues',
[74] and that the 'divine
sign' is too rare to save most of them from corruption: 'My own divine
sign, I think, hardly counts, as hardly anyone before me has had it.'
[75]
The picture we have of Socrates' character, independent of mysticism and
philosophy, is that of a frugal and hardy nature, at home in the army
or in discussion with citizens from the humblest cobbler to the statesmen
of the time, a welcome guest at a drinking party, and always with
people (there is nothing in Plato to suggest that Socrates was any kind
of recluse). None of this fits well with a man who "has no time to
look at the affairs of men"; on the contrary he is passionately interested
in men, and even mentions in the Phaedrus: "Now the people
in the city have something to teach me, but the fields and trees won't
teach me anything." [76]
But the last thing that his involvement with the citizens of Athens seems
to be about in his actual life is to (a) rule them and (b) withdraw to
solitary contemplation to achieve that.
The Utopian nature of The Republic would be an odd note for any
mystic to strike, because of their insistence on the 'other world' (or
non-material reality) if via negativa (and this is Socrates' theme
in the Phaedo) or their insistence on the natural world as it
is if via positiva. A more typical response to politics is
Jesus' "Render unto Caesar that which is Caesar's" (and incidentally
the source of much popular criticism, from Martin Scorcese's The Last
Temptation of Christ to Monty Python's The Life of Brian).
Socrates tells us in the Apology that he quit politics in fact
because he wanted a long life. So is The Republic a musing by a
mystic on an ideal society? If so, then why make the assumption: "So
philosophy is impossible among the common people."? [77] Surely the ideal society for a mystic
is one where everyone is lead to 'philosophy' (read mysticism for now)?
But the ideal state we learn of is strictly stratiated into the philosopher-kings,
the auxiliaries (those who are not full philosophers but carry out the
running of the state and its defence) and the common people, farmers,
tradesmen and so on.
But worse is to come. The ideal state as described in The Republic
is quite clearly totalitarian, in fact differing from historical examples
only by the replacement of a fascist dictator with one or more philosopher-kings.
The rulers in Socrates' version are of course benign, but the instruments
they use are recognisably totalitarian: the strict control over education
(especially reading material), the issue of propaganda in the form of
suitable 'myths', the censorship of the arts and its subordination to
the goals of the state, and the practice of eugenics, including infanticide.
Even enthusiastic Plato scholars admit that these elements are problematic,
but since the second world war a number of commentators have focused in
more depth on the totalitarianism in The Republic (though not from
the perspective of mysticism). These include Toynbee's A Study of History,
R.H.S. Crossman's Plato Today, and Bertrand Russell's Philosophy
and Politics. However, Sir Karl Popper has been the most vociferous
critic, in his The Open Society and its Enemies. He examines the
views of a number of Plato apologists and comes to this conclusion: "In
spite of such arguments, I believe that Plato's political programme, far
from being morally superior to totalitarianism, is fundamentally identical
to it." [78] Popper believes that Plato was reacting to the Heraclitean philosophy
of flux, and was seeking the "possibility of arresting all
political change". [79] I.M.Crombie, on the other hand, suggests that Plato was
trying to find an accommodation between "the theories of Heraclitus
and the practice of Socrates." [80]
A good coverage of the arguments for and against Plato as a totalitarian
are to be found in Plato, Popper, and Politics, a collection of
fifteen essays by scholars across the spectrum of opinion, including Popper.
[81] In one of these essays G.R.Morrow
makes this point: "Now the heart and centre of the Nazi and Communist
admiration for Plato, and of the American liberal's repudiation of him,
is of course, the idealization of absolutism in the Republic, the
doctrine that government is a high art that can only be entrusted to an
elite group, who must not be hampered by the rules that men call laws."
[82] Morrow goes on to defend Plato by pointing out that in
Laws (a much later work) Plato modifies this stance by saying "There
is no mortal soul that can bear supreme and irresponsible power without
losing his wisdom and integrity," (Laws 691c), and providing
a whole system of laws that would provide the necessary checks and balances.
Where this defence falls down, I think, is that in real life laws arise
out of the affairs of men, rather than from the Gods, as Plato states
at the outset of the Laws (624a). However, this argument is not
central to our enquiry, and I wish only to make one more comment on the
Laws: that by the very laws on impiety that Plato proposes in this
late work (Laws 909) Socrates would have been condemned to death,
despite the defence by Plato in the early work the Apology. (I
challenge anyone to prove otherwise, except in the case that Plato himself
is the prosecutor.)
Returning to eugenics (the science of improving the human stock, according
to Sir Francis Galton, coiner of the term in 1883 [83]),
we find that in the post-Nazi era the term has thankfully a negative connotation,
but it is easy to forget that for many so-called liberals in the early
part of the twentieth century it was seen as an answer to many of society's
ills. Huxley and Orwell subscribed to it and so did Sir Winston Churchill,
and it is only due to the veto of his cabinet that he failed to implement
policies of selective sterilisation of criminals and gypsies. Oddly enough,
despite the substantial section of the Republic devoted to eugenic
ideas, Galton makes no mention of the Republic, and neither do
any of the other texts I have consulted on the subject.
2.2.7.
Preliminary Conclusions on Plato's Socrates
As stated earlier, The Republic gives us many elements that contribute
to the portrait of Socrates as mystic (and the famous analogies of the
Sun, the Line, and the Cave in The Republic are good examples),
but the overall picture of its intent is anti-mystical. For while it may
be possible to find another mystic with a Utopian outlook (I don't know
of one), I don't believe it possible to find one with a totalitarian outlook.
From this perspective it seems more likely that Plato himself was not
a mystic, but reported at times with sensitivity on Socrates who was.
Plato's intentions change throughout his works; as the direct influence
of his master waned (Plato's Academy was founded about fourteen years
after Socrates' death for example) Plato's concerns became more political.
Before drawing any final conclusions however we should look at the other
major source on Socrates' life, Xenophon.
2.3. Xenophon
Xenophon was an exact contemporary of Plato, being aged 29 when Socrates
died (at the age of 70); Plato was 28. Xenophon was a country gentleman,
a military man, and a historian, and provides us with a quite detailed
portrait of Socrates through four dialogues, known in the Penguin translation
as Socrates' Defence, Memoirs of Socrates, The Dinner-Party,
and The Estate Manager. Socrates' Defence is the equivalent
of Plato's Apology, and The Dinner-Party is the equivalent
of Plato's Symposium (the differences in translation of the titles
seem arbitrary but are useful in distinguishing the works of the two authors).
The portrait of Socrates from Xenophon has none of the contradictions
of Plato, none of the totalitarianism, and little indication of mysticism.
Xenophon was a pragmatist with a utilitarian approach, a doer rather than
a thinker, but with a sensitivity to the good that he found so
developed in Socrates, albeit a good that must translate into the
affairs of men and whose worth is judged from that perspective. His agenda
is seen most plainly in The Estate Manager, though it is present
in all the dialogues. John Philips Potter considers that "The opinions
and conduct of Socrates may be safely estimated from Xenophon ... [he]
respected his master too religiously to dare to interpolate any thing
into his opinions." [84]
This is probably a little optimistic; scholars down the ages have in fact
argued for and against Xenophon's evidence, those arguing for (like Potter)
on the basis that he was not independent enough of thought to interpolate,
while those arguing against on the basis that he was not intelligent enough
to understand Socrates. From the point of view of mysticism we learn little,
not because Xenophon was not intelligent, but because he was clearly not
mystically inclined. However, the consistency and pragmatism of Xenophon
do give us a better picture of Socrates as a man than does Plato.
Xenophon's portrait shows us a Socrates who is visible (i.e. always
amongst people), temperate (in all things, and in a highly considered
manner), humorous (hilariously so at times, as when he calls himself
a pimp [85] , and when he engages
in a beauty competition with Critobulus [86]), engaging (in the sense of
reaching out to actual and potential disciples), democratic (despite
his association with aristocrats and tyrants), interested (in human
affairs), and positive (he teaches piety through gratitude for
a munificent universe). This passage shows his liking for company:
Moreover,
he was always visible. For in the early morning he used to go on walks
and to the gymnasium, and when the marketplace was full he was visible
there, and for the remainder of the day he was always where he might
be with the most people. [87]
Xenophon also shows a Socrates who is conventionally religious in his
observances and obedience to religious law, though possessed in addition
with the power of divination. Beyond this Xenophon does not speculate
on areas we might consider mystical, and gives only a brief account of
Socrates' philosophy:
I shall
now try to describe how Socrates made his associates better at philosophical
discussion. He believed that those who understood the nature of
any given thing would be able to explain it to others as well, whereas
it was no wonder, he said, if those who did not understand made
mistakes themselves and misled other. Consequently, he never stopped
investigating with the help of his companions the meaning of every
single term. It would be laborious task to describe fully all the
distinctions he drew; I shall mention only a few examples, which
I think will serve to illustrate his method of inquiry. [88]
It is clear
that while Xenophon had enormous respect for Socrates he was not interested
in the 'laborious task' of reproducing his teachings. The essence of Xenophon's
respect is probably captured in the passage where Lycon says at the end
of The Dinner Party "I swear, Socrates, it does seem to me
that you are a truly good man." [89]
Given Xenophon's character, there is nothing in his testimony that works
against Socrates as mystic: around every great Master there are always
those who are devoted and loyal but whose temperament inclines them to
the practical and away from the mystical. However, although there is little
directly mystical in Xenophon's portrait there are some pointers here
and there, beyond the obvious references to Socrates' daimon. Firstly,
Socrates had an estranging effect (allegedly) on his followers from their
parents and relatives, reminiscent of a similar charge against Jesus:
Socrates'
accuser said that he lowered the regard of his associates not
only for their fathers, but also for their other relatives, by
saying that it is not their relatives that help the victim of
disease or litigation but doctors in the one case and competent
advocates in the other. [90]
Socrates
clearly believed that he offered something unique to his disciples that
their relatives could not, and that it was as urgent as if they were facing
disease or litigation. However he balances this elsewhere by praising
the role of the parent, for example when remonstrating with his own son
(who is indignant at his treatment from his mother Xanthippe). [91]
That the word 'disciple' may be better used for 'associates' (found in
most translations) is illustrated by the way in which Euthydemus is shown
by Socrates to have no 'real' knowledge, his initial dejection at this
and abandonment of Socrates' company, only to return: "and from that
time onwards, he never left him unless he was obliged to, and he even
copied some of Socrates' practices." [92] In Xenophon, unlike in Plato, we find that Socrates uses
what is known much later as the 'argument from design' to instil piety
in his followers, and this is used on Euthydemus, taking up the whole
of section 4.3 of the Memoirs of Socrates. This is too long to
quote in full, but some of the positive and almost prayerful tone is captured
in this passage:
And
what of the fact that they [the gods] have equipped us with senses
appropriate to the different kinds of beautiful and beneficial objects
that surround us, so that by means of these senses we can enjoy
all good things? And the fact that they have implanted in us reason,
which enables us to think about and remember our sensations, and
so discover the beneficial effects of each class of objects and
devise various means for enjoying what is good and avoiding what
is bad for us? [93]
In another parallel with Jesus, we find Socrates visiting a prostitute
(or so we are meant to assume from the fact that she maintained a large
household solely from the favours of wealthy men; perhaps 'courtesan'
would be a better word). This is described in section 3.11 of the Memoirs,
and finishes with the following exchange:
Theodote
said, 'Why don't you help me in my hunt for friends, Socrates?
'I will, believe me', said Socrates, 'if you persuade me.'
'How can I persuade you?'
'You'll look to that yourself,' he said, 'and you'll find a way,
if you need any help from me.'
'Then come and see me often,' she said.
'Well, Theodote,' replied Socrates, poking fun at his own avoidance
of public life, 'it's not very easy for me to find the time for
it. I have a great deal of public and private business that keeps
me occupied and I have some girlfriends too, who will never let
me leave them by day or night, because they are learning from me
about love-charms and spells.'
'Do you really know about them too, Socrates?' she asked.
'Why do you suppose that Apollodorus here and Antisthenes never
leave me? And that Cebes and Simmias come to visit me from Thebes?
You may be sure that these things don't happen without a lot of
love-charms and spells and magic wheels.'
'Lend me your magic wheel, then, so that I may spin it first for
you.'
'Certainly not,' he said. 'I don't want to be drawn to you; I want
you to come to me.'
'Very well, I will,' she declared. 'Only mind you let me in.'
'Yes, I'll let you in,' said Socrates, 'unless I have someone with
me that I like better.' [94]
Socrates' 'girlfriends' are, of course, his disciples, and we can read
this passage as the good-humoured 'fishing' for a new disciple that spiritual
Masters are continuously engaged in. Socrates is clear that she must come
to him and not the other way round though.
We also have a possible reference in Xenophon to one of Socrates' 'fits
of abstraction', or, in our terms samadhi. Socrates is talking
about dancing:
'...
Don't you know that the other day Charmides here caught me dancing
at daybreak?'
'Yes,
indeed I did,' said Charmides, 'and at first I was astonished and
afraid that you were out of your mind, but, when I heard you explain
it to me in the way that you are doing now, I went home myself and
well, I didn't dance, because I've never learned how, but I waved
my arms about, because I knew how to do that!' [95]
If, and I grant that this is a big if, Socrates was prone to the
kind of samadhi so well-documented in the case of Ramakrishna,
then we can expect him to sometimes be still (as recorded in Plato) and
sometimes to move in rapture, perhaps to 'wave' his arms about. Given
that samadhi has not been widely understood in the West, and that
it is rare occurrence anyway, we can expect both that witnesses may confuse
it with dancing, and that Socrates may have encouraged this view because
he had no other way of explaining it, or did not want to dwell on it.
None of the evidence from Xenophon is conclusive about Socrates' status
as mystic of course, but we have seen that many passages can be read that
way. What Xenophon gives us, and which I think is relatively reliable
because of its consistency, is a quality of Socrates of balance.
He is temperate, but does not approve of neglecting the body, he is humorous,
but never at someone else's expense, he is curt if absolutely necessary
(as with the entertainment manager at the Dinner-Party [96]),
he is interested in human affairs to the degree that they can be made
to embody the good, and above all seems equal to any situation
(as we see with both the courtesan and at his trial).
3. Conclusions
3.1. Plato as Philosopher or Mystic
Having looked at the picture of Socrates drawn by Plato and Xenophon,
we must come to a conclusion as to whether we can reasonably regard Socrates
as a mystic. Because the main evidence for his mysticism comes from Plato,
we need to carefully consider whether Plato himself was the mystic. While
disagreeing with many of Bharati's claims, I think he has a valid point
in saying that mystics are totally absorbed in mysticism (it was from
this perspective that he made the comment on having no small-talk mentioned
earlier). Plato, in his writings, certainly seems to show a mystical sensitivity
in some passages, but these are mitigated against by his utopian, political,
and totalitarian views in other passages. We can then propose two Platos;
one is the mystic interested in immortality, the 'good', and the essence
behind reality (the 'forms'), and the other is interested in a political
solution to the problems of the contemporary State, based on 'philosopher-kings'.
Conventionally these two Platos could be seen as complementary, and directly
related, in the Western guise of 'philosopher', but from the history of
mysticism this is not supportable. When a mystic expands the stage on
which they teach or transmit their mystical wisdom, it is to give access
to these teachings for the many, and not to create a constitution which
limits this to a few and keeps the many in ignorance through the deliberate
creation of myths and propaganda.
The Socratic dialogues of Plato, taken on their own, might leave us in
doubt about the two Platos I propose here, but I think that if we add
works such as the Laws, and, more importantly, his famous Seventh
Letter, we are forced to choose Plato the politician. In the Seventh
Letter he says: "When I was a young man I expected, like many
others, to embark, as soon as I was my own master, on a political career."
[97] We find that the political upheavals
in Athens culminating in the execution of Socrates turned Plato to philosophy
and formed his conviction that "the troubles of mankind will never
cease until either true and genuine philosophers attain political power
or the rulers of states by some dispensation of providence become genuine
philosophers." [98] The Seventh Letter documents Plato's only, and disastrous,
attempt to help put this into practice. Plato as a politician was then
a failure, but as a political philosopher he ranks amongst those with
the greatest and longest influence in the West. Bertrand Russell considers
in fact that we are bequeathed five great philosophical contributions
from Plato: (1) his Utopia, (2) his theory of ideas [forms], (3) his argument
in favour of immortality, (4) his cosmogony, (5) his conception of knowledge
as reminiscence rather than perception. [99]
While philosophers (in the modern sense) clearly claim Plato to be of
their own kind, others do claim Plato as mystic. Happold for example states
that Plato is the 'Father of Christian Mysticism' [100], but this is hard to support: Eckhart (as jnani)
may have drawn elements from Plato, but Rolle (as bhakti) did not.
The evidence collected here does not support the view that Plato himself
was a mystic.
3.2. Plato's Socratic Dialogues as a Proximity
Text
If Plato is not himself a mystic, then we can consider his Socratic dialogues
as constituting a proximity text as defined above. We know that Plato
was only 28 when Socrates died, and that probably the bulk of his writings
took place later than this, right into Plato's old age. Hence the early
dialogues are probably the most reliable (as Vlastos points out in a slightly
different context) as proximity texts. Do we find the contradictions,
misunderstandings and adumbrations that we might expect in a proximity
text in Plato? Of course we do. But, when we consider Plato's own genius,
his mercurial mind (as shown in the great range of his subject matter,
compared to say Xenophon), and the very definite evolving agenda of his
own, we must say that it is not a proximity text of the first rank. While
one might at first consider Plato's total absence as a character anywhere
in his dialogues as the sort of modesty that led Mahendranath to give
only the letter 'M' in authorship to his Gospel of Ramakrishna,
one gradually realises that it is not due to modesty. Otherwise why should
he use Socrates so barefacedly for his own evolving agenda? The absence
of Plato is partly the style of the time (Xenophon, by contrast, appears
several times in his dialogues, and gives his own opinions), but I find
it a little dishonest.
A comparison has been made by Colin Wilson between the Plato/Socrates
relationship and the Ouspensky/Gurdjieff one, [101] and commented upon by Georg Feuerstein [102] in the context of what he calls
'holy madness' or the rascal guru (Socrates as rascal guru is not so preposterous:
think of his humorous claim to be a pimp). Ouspensky is very honest about
his shortcomings with respect to the knowledge that Gurdjieff possesses,
as this quote from In Search of the Miraculous shows (Gurdjieff
is speaking):
"A
great deal can be found by reading. For instance, take yourself: you
might already know a great deal if you knew how to read. I mean
that, if you understood everything that you have read in your
life, you would already know what you are looking for now. If you understood
everything you have written in your book, what is it called?" he
made something altogether impossible out of the words "Tertium
Organum" "I should come and bow down to you and beg you to
teach me. But you do not understand either what you read or what
you write." [103]
Ouspensky
was a noted, though not mainstream, philosopher at the turn of the century,
and rather immodestly titled his first major work Tertium Organum
after Bacon's Novum Organum and Aristotle's Organum. His
encounter with Gurdjieff may well have something in common with that between
Plato and Socrates. It is not impossible to imagine Socrates making a
similar comment to the one above on Plato's writings. However, Ouspensky
devoted his later life to Gurdjieff, who gave his blessing to In Search
of the Miraculous as an accurate summary of his teachings. It stands
therefore as one of the best examples of a proximity text, alongside The
Gospel of Ramakrishna. Plato's dialogues, on the evidence here stated,
are a lesser case: his agenda is much further from Socrates' than Ouspensky's
was from Gurdjieff's.
3.3. Xenophon's Evidence
If Plato's dialogues are a lesser case of a proximity text, then what
of Xenophon's? They are, for sure, more consistent, and Xenophon's agenda
is less intrusive and variable than Plato's, but there is not a lot of
evidence for mysticism there. What is valuable is a warm and breathing
portrait of Socrates as a man, all of which is consistent with
him as mystic, but not proof. Given that a proximity text should at least
in part set out to show the subject as mystic, we cannot give this status
to Xenophon's dialogues, because Xenophon plainly is not conversant with
or interested in the essential elements of mysticism, as Plato is.
3.4. Socrates as Mystic
How then shall we answer our question, is Socrates a mystic? If forced
to a straight yes or no, then a yes is probably required on the evidence
presented here. On the other hand we see that our evidence from Plato
constitutes a lesser proximity text (as defined in this dissertation)
and that we cannot count Xenophon's dialogues as a proximity text, though
a useful portrait of the man. Clearly then, while we can add Socrates
as a 'possible' to our roll-call of mystics, his is not the clear case
that we derive where there are substantial first-order proximity texts
or primary texts.
There are many useful issues that Socrates' case does raise for mysticism
however. One of these is the whole concept of the jnani mystic
in the West, and the relation of this to bhakti.
3.5. Socrates and Jesus
We can consider the relationship between jnani and bhakti
in the context of comparisons made between Socrates and Jesus. In R.M.Wenley's
Socrates and Christ he cites 'an extreme view' of R.W.Mackay: "To
the truth already uttered in the Athenian prison, Christianity added little
or nothing; except a few symbols, which though perhaps well calculated
for popular acceptance, are more likely to perplex than instruct, and
offer the best opportunity for priestly mystification." [104]
Wenley's book attempts a refutation of this view, conceding the parallels,
but concluding that they "hold of externals rather than essentials."
[105] Montuori tells us that
it was Justinius the Martyr who first established the parallels, and that
reaction in Christian thought was generally divided between those who
agreed and those who saw the teachings on immortality as pagan [106].
If we accept Socrates as jnani and perhaps the preceding mysticism
of Heraclitus and Pythagoras as the same, then the impact of Christ on
the West can be seen in terms of bhakti. There is no need then
to see a rivalry between the two, or to labour over the parallels between
the mens' lives and teachings (some of which we have pointed out here).
From this perspective Christ brought to the Hellenic and Roman world a
devotional outlook that took hold in a way that previous devotional practices
had not. At the same time it could be said that it swept away the older
jnani understandings, or rather forced them underground.
3.6. Jnani, Gnosis, and Philosophy in
the West
But perhaps it was Plato that planted the seeds of the demise of jnani.
If, as Popper claims, Plato was trying to find a bulwark against the Heraclitean
flux, then it is in the philosophical element in Plato, not the mystical,
that jnani became less understood. Brickhouse and Smith wish to
make the dichotomy between divination and ratiocination, arguing against
Vlastos that Socrates prioritised the former against the latter [107]. But I believe that the issue is much
more subtle, and is better characterised as a dichotomy between philosophy
(understood as ratiocination, or cogitation) and jnani. In James
Beckman's The Religious Dimension of Socrates' Thought we find
again that the dichotomy is between divination and ratiocination (expressed
by Beckman as between religion and philosophy): he points out that "no
philosopher, for instance, ever recommended praying to his philosophical
ultimate." [108] If we accept the basis of jnani as non-devotional,
then prayer does not come into it; instead we are in the territory of
meditation, a defined in this dissertation.
Plato is in fact the source, or a source, of two mystical traditions in
the West with a jnani orientation; Neoplatonism, and the Gnostic
tradition. I would suggest that the confusion in Plato between philosophy
(as we now understand it) and jnani is one reason why these traditions
are not widely understood today. The rise of the devotional religion of
Christianity is another reason.
3.7. Further Research
I believe that this inquiry into the possible mystical status of Socrates
has brought to light some important further questions for mysticism in
the West, as outlined above. An examination of Buddhist thought would
be useful in this context for the fine-grained distinctions between ratiocination
(or cogitation) and meditation, and the role of thought in preparing the
mind for silence of the mind. This would help place Western philosophy
in context. A clearer picture of the Indian view on jnani would
be useful, and the exploration of Neoplatonism and Gnosticism in terms
of the Buddhist and Hindu concepts would be valuable. Finally it might
be possible to better judge the true role of jnani in the development
of the West (giving us a better understanding of Eckhart for example)
and its relationship with devotional mysticism.
As I have argued both for a clear distinction between jnani and
bhakti and for their inseparable intertwining, perhaps one could
find a route to the devotional for our predominantly lay culture through
a better understanding of jnani. Our understanding of Socrates
is dependent on the distinction between jnani and bhakti,
and I believe that it is central to all understanding of mysticism.
References for Part 5
[73]
Plato, The
Republic, Trans.: Desmond Lee, London: Penguin Books, 1987, p. 236
[74] Plato,
The Republic, Trans.: Desmond Lee, London: Penguin Books, 1987,
p. 225
[75] Plato,
The Republic, Trans.: Desmond Lee, London: Penguin Books, 1987,
p. 231
[76] Plato,
Phaedrus and Letters VII and VIII, Trans.: Walter Hamilton, Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1973, p. 26
[77] Plato,
The Republic, Trans.: Desmond Lee, London: Penguin Books, 1987,
p. 228
[78] Popper,
Karl R. The Open Society and its Enemies, London: Routledge, 1945,
Vol. 1, p. 75
[79] Popper,
Karl R. The Open Society and its Enemies, London: Routledge, 1945,
Vol. 1, p. 16
[80] Crombie,
I.M., Plato, the Midwife's Apprentice, London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1964, p. 11
[81] Mambrough,
Renford, (Ed.) Plato, Popper and Politics, Cambridge: Heffer, New
York: Barnes and Noble, 1967.
[82] Morrow,
G.R., 'Plato and the Rule of Law' in Mambrough, Renford, (Ed.)
Plato, Popper and Politics, Cambridge: Heffer, New York: Barnes
and Noble, 1967, p. 106
[83] Galton,
Sir Francis, Essays in Eugenics, London: The Eugenics Society (Garland),
1909, p. 75
[84] Potter,
John Philips, The Religion of Socrates, London: B. Fellows, 1831,
footnote to p.10
[85] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, The Dinner Party 3.10, p. 238
[86] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, The Dinner Party section 5.
[87] Xenophon,
Memorabilia, Trans.: Amy L. Bonnette, Icatha and London: Cornell
University Press, 1994, p. 3
[88] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, Memoirs of Socrates 4.6.1, p. 205
[89] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, The Dinner Party 9.7, p. 265
[90] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, Memoirs of Socrates, 1.2.47, p. 82
[91] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, Memoirs of Socrates, 2.2, p. 109
[92] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, Memoirs of Socrates, p. 190, see also the
whole of section 4.2, starting p. 178
[93] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, Memoirs of Socrates, p. 193
[94] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, Memoirs of Socrates, p. 170
[95] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, The Dinner Party 2.19, p. 234
[96] Xenophon,
Conversations of Socrates, Trans.: Hugh Tredennick and Robin Waterfield,
London: Penguin, 1990, The Dinner Party 6.8, p. 256
[97] Plato,
Phaedrus and Letters VII and VIII, Trans.: Walter Hamilton, Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1973, p. 112
[98] Plato,
Phaedrus and Letters VII and VIII, Trans.: Walter Hamilton, Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1973,p. 114
[99] Russell,
Bertrand, A History of Western Philosophy, London, Sidney, Wellington:
Unwin Paperbacks, 1989, p. 122
[100] Happold,
F.C. Mysticism - a Study and and Anthology, Penguin Books, London,
1970, p. 176
[101] Wilson,
Colin, The Outsider, London: Picador, 1978, p. 277
[102] Feuerstein,
Georg. Holy Madness, London: Arkana, 1990, p. 55
[103] Ouspensky,
P.D. In Search of the Miraculous - Fragments of an Unknown Teaching,
Arkana, p. 20
[104] Wenley,
R.M. Socrates and Christ, Edinburgh and London: Blackwood, 1889,
p. 6
[105] Wenley,
R.M. Socrates and Christ, Edinburgh and London: Blackwood, 1889,
p. 9
[106] Montuori,
Mario, Socrates-Physiology of a Myth', Amsterdam: J.C.Gieben, 1981,
p. 6 and 7
[107] Brickhouse,
Thomas, and Smith, Nicholas, Plato's Socrates, New York, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, p. 190
[108] Beckman,
James, The Religious Dimension of Socrates' Thought, Waterloo,
Ontario: Wilfred Laurier University Press, 1979, p. 172
>
back
|